[ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]
reason to think that justice is no natural virtue in this system. (IHM II, vi [109b; B 35]) chapter x In Conclusion: Living Wisely in the Darkness two thomases: aquinas and reid Having opened his Summa contra gentiles with some reflections on the office of the wise man, and having remarked that among all human pursuits, the pursuit of wisdom is more perfect, more noble, more useful, and more full of joy than any other (I,2,2), Thomas Aquinas, in a passage unusual in his work for its use of the first person singular pronoun, goes on to declare that in the name of the divine Mercy, I have the confidence to embark upon the work of a wise man, even though this may surpass my powers (I,2,2).1 That work, he says, is the work of making known . . . the truth that the Catholic faith professes, and of setting aside the errors that are opposed to it (I,2,2). What follows these intro- ductory comments is four rather lengthy books in which Aquinas articulates Christian theology in the manner of a scientia, polemi- cizing along the way against alternative positions. Why does Aquinas think that articulating Christian theology in scientific fashion, and polemicizing against alternatives, is a way of exercising the office of a wise person? After citing Aristotle to authorize his adherence to common usage, Aquinas remarks that the usage of the multitude . . . has commonly held that they are to be called wise who order things rightly and govern them well. He supports his view on this point of usage by appealing to Aris- totle on this matter as well, remarking that among other things that men have conceived about the wise man, the Philosopher includes the notion that it belongs to the wise man to order (I,1,1). 1 I am quoting from the translation by Anton C. Pegis, issued by the University of Notre Dame Press (Notre Dame, Ind.) in 1975. 250 Conclusion 251 With this concept of the wise person in hand, Aquinas proceeds to highlight some structural features of the practical arts and their relation to each other. The rule of government and order for all things directed to an end must be taken from that end, he says. For, since the end of each thing is its good, a thing is then best disposed when it is fittingly ordered to its end. Accordingly, a condition of being a wise person within some practical art is knowing the end, the goal, the telos, of that practice. Now most artisans are of course concerned with the ends of certain par- ticular things, they do not reach to the universal end of all things. They are therefore said to be wise with respect to this or that thing (I,1,1). It is to be noted, however, that the various practices to be found in human society do not constitute a mere assemblage; many are related to each other as subordinate to superordinate. One functions as the governor and the ruler of another because it controls its end. Thus, the art of medicine rules and orders the art of the [pharmacist] because health, with which medicine is concerned, is the end of all the medications prepared by the art of the [pharmacist] (I,1,1). Suppose, then, that there is an ultimate human telos; suppose even that there is a telos of the universe and all that dwells therein. The name of the absolutely wise man . . . is reserved for him whose considera- tion is directed to the end of the universe, which is also the origin of the universe (I,1,1). Aquinas s idea presupposed rather than expressed is that the person who possesses knowledge of the ultimate end of all things in general, and of all practices in par- ticular, will be of important if not indispensable aid to all those who, in their ordering and governing activities, deal with more limited ends. When Aquinas declared that he would be so bold as to exercise the office of the wise person, it was of the office of the absolutely wise person that he was thinking. He would reflect on the end of all things which is God. Thus it is that what follows these intro- ductory comments is a theological treatise. Of course, anyone who has read beyond the first book of the Summa contra gentiles knows that Aquinas speaks not just of God but of created things as well. That s because theology is not just about God; it s also about the cosmos and all things to be found therein insofar as they are related to God. Correspondingly, it was not medical wisdom, political wisdom, 252 Thomas Reid and the Story of Epistemology engineering wisdom, and so forth, that Aquinas had in mind when he said that the pursuit of wisdom is more perfect, more noble, more useful, and more full of joy than any other human
[ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ] zanotowane.pldoc.pisz.plpdf.pisz.plgrolux.keep.pl
|